David Benatar
David Benatar | |
---|---|
Born | 1966 (age 58–59) South Africa[2] |
Occupation(s) | Academic, professor, writer |
Known for | Antinatalism |
Academic background | |
Education | University of Cape Town (BSocSc, PhD) |
Academic work | |
Discipline | Philosophy |
Sub-discipline | |
Institutions | University of Cape Town |
Notable works | Better Never to Have Been (2006) |
Notable ideas | Benatar's asymmetry argument |
David Benatar (/ˈbɛnətɑːr/;[3] born 1966) is a South African philosopher, academic, and author. He is best known for his work in moral philosophy and for advancing the position of antinatalism, the view that coming into existence is a serious harm. He is the author of Better Never to Have Been: The Harm of Coming into Existence (2006), in which he argues that procreation is always morally wrong because it imposes harm by bringing sentient beings into existence. Central to this view is his asymmetry argument, which holds that the absence of pain is good even if no one benefits from it, while the absence of pleasure is not bad unless someone is deprived of it.
Benatar has also written on topics including death, ethics, human suffering, and gender discrimination. He is emeritus professor of philosophy at the University of Cape Town and a member of the editorial board of the Journal of Controversial Ideas.
Education and career
[edit]Benatar is the son of Solomon Benatar, a global-health expert who founded the Bioethics Centre at the University of Cape Town. He studied at the University of Cape Town, receiving a BSocSc and PhD.[1]
Benatar is emeritus professor of philosophy at the University of Cape Town.[1] He is a member of the editorial board of the Journal of Controversial Ideas.[4]
Philosophical work
[edit]Asymmetry between pain and pleasure
[edit]Benatar argues there is a crucial asymmetry between the good and the bad things, such as pleasure and pain, which means it would be better for humans not to have been born:[5][6]
- The presence of pain is bad.
- The presence of pleasure is good.
- The absence of pain is good, even if that good is not enjoyed by anyone.
- The absence of pleasure is not bad unless there is somebody for whom this absence is a deprivation.
Scenario A (X exists) | Scenario B (X never exists) |
---|---|
1. Presence of pain (Bad) | 3. Absence of pain (Good) |
2. Presence of pleasure (Good) | 4. Absence of pleasure (Not bad) |
Implications for procreation
[edit]Benatar argues that bringing someone into existence generates both good and bad experiences, pain and pleasure, whereas not doing so generates neither pain nor pleasure. The absence of pain is good, while the absence of pleasure is not bad. Therefore, the ethical choice is weighed in favor of non-procreation.[7]
Benatar raises four other related asymmetries that he considers quite plausible:[7]
- We have a moral obligation not to create unhappy people and we have no moral obligation to create happy people. The reason why we think there is a moral obligation not to create unhappy people is that the presence of this suffering would be bad (for the sufferers) and the absence of the suffering is good (even though there is nobody to enjoy the absence of suffering). By contrast, the reason we think there is no moral obligation to create happy people is that although their pleasure would be good for them, the absence of pleasure when they do not come into existence will not be bad, because there will be no one who will be deprived of this good.
- It is strange to mention the interests of a potential child as a reason why we decide to create them, and it is not strange to mention the interests of a potential child as a reason why we decide not to create them. That the child may be happy is not a morally important reason to create them. By contrast, that the child may be unhappy is an important moral reason not to create them. If it were the case that the absence of pleasure is bad even if someone does not exist to experience its absence, then we would have a significant moral reason to create a child and to create as many children as possible. And if it were not the case that the absence of pain is good even if someone does not exist to experience this good, then we would not have a significant moral reason not to create a child.
- Someday we can regret the sake of a person whose existence was conditional on our decision, that we created them – a person can be unhappy and the presence of their pain would be a bad thing. But we will never feel regret for the sake of a person whose existence was conditional on our decision, that we did not create them – a person will not be deprived of happiness, because he or she will never exist, and the absence of happiness will not be bad, because there will be no one who will be deprived of this good.
- We feel sadness by the fact that somewhere people come into existence and suffer, and we feel no sadness by the fact that somewhere people did not come into existence in a place where there are happy people. When we know that somewhere people came into existence and suffer, we feel compassion. The fact that on some deserted island or planet, people did not come into existence and suffer is good. This is because the absence of pain is good even when there is not someone who is experiencing this good. On the other hand, we do not feel sadness by the fact that on some deserted island or planet, people did not come into existence and are not happy. This is because the absence of pleasure is bad only when someone exists to be deprived of this good.
Humans' unreliable assessment of life's quality
[edit]Benatar raises the issue of whether humans inaccurately estimate the true quality of their lives, and has cited three psychological phenomena which he believes are responsible for this:[8]
- Tendency towards optimism: we have a positively distorted perspective of our lives in the past, present, and future.
- Adaptation: we adapt to our circumstances, and if they worsen, our sense of well-being is lowered in anticipation of those harmful circumstances, according to our expectations, which are usually divorced from the reality of our circumstances.
- Comparison: we judge our lives by comparing them to those of others, ignoring the negatives which affect everyone to focus on specific differences. And due to our optimism bias, we mostly compare ourselves to those worse off, to overestimate the value of our own well-being.
He concludes:[8]
The above psychological phenomena are unsurprising from an evolutionary perspective. They militate against suicide and in favour of reproduction. If our lives are quite as bad as I shall still suggest they are, and if people were prone to see this true quality of their lives for what it is, they might be much more inclined to kill themselves, or at least not to produce more such lives. Pessimism, then, tends not to be naturally selected.
Badness of death
[edit]In The Human Predicament (2017), Benatar presents three arguments for why death can be regarded as bad. The first focuses on the suffering commonly associated with dying, which often involves physical pain and emotional distress for both the individual and those close to them. The second, known as the "deprivation account", holds that death is harmful because it deprives individuals of future experiences, including potential pleasures and achievements, regardless of whether their life as a whole is positive or negative. The third argument considers death bad in itself, as it results in the complete and irreversible annihilation of the self, ending psychological continuity and biographical identity. Benatar suggests that these considerations can justify a rational fear of death, independent of cultural or religious attitudes toward mortality.[9]
Discrimination against men and boys
[edit]Benatar's book The Second Sexism: Discrimination Against Men and Boys (2012) examines various issues regarding misandry and the negative socially imposed aspects of male identity. It does not seek to attack or diminish the ideas of feminism, but rather to shine a light on the parallel existence of systemic and cultural discrimination against men and boys. In a review of the book, philosopher Simon Blackburn writes that "Benatar knows that such examples are likely to meet snorts of disbelief or derision, but he is careful to back up his claims with empirical data," and through this book, he shows that "if it is all too often tough being a woman, it is also sometimes tough being a man, and that any failure to recognise this risks distorting what should be everyone's goal, namely universal sympathy as well as social justice for all, regardless of gender."[10] In another review, the philosopher Iddo Landau praises the work as "a very well-argued book that presents an unorthodox thesis and defends it ably," agreeing with Benatar that "in order to cope with the hitherto ignored second sexism, we should not only acknowledge it, but also dedicate much more empirical and philosophical research to this under-explored topic and, of course, try to change many attitudes, social norms, and laws".[11]
Publications
[edit]Benatar is the author of a series of widely cited papers in medical ethics, including "Between Prophylaxis and Child Abuse" (The American Journal of Bioethics)[12] and "A Pain in the Fetus: Toward Ending Confusion about Fetal Pain" (Bioethics), both co-authored with Michael Benatar.[13] His work has been published in journals including Ethics, Journal of Applied Philosophy, Social Theory and Practice, American Philosophical Quarterly, QJM: An International Journal of Medicine, Journal of Law and Religion and the British Medical Journal.[14]
Cultural influence
[edit]Nic Pizzolatto, creator and writer of True Detective, has cited Benatar's Better Never to Have Been as an influence on the TV series (along with Ray Brassier's Nihil Unbound, Thomas Ligotti's The Conspiracy Against the Human Race, Jim Crawford's Confessions of an Antinatalist, and Eugene Thacker's In the Dust of This Planet).[15]
Personal life
[edit]Benatar is known for maintaining a high level of personal privacy, and little is publicly known about his private life. He has held antinatalist views since his childhood.[2] He has stated that he does not have children.[16][17]
Benatar is vegan, and has taken part in debates on veganism.[18] He has argued that humans are "responsible for the suffering and deaths of billions of other humans and non-human animals. If that level of destruction were caused by another species we would rapidly recommend that new members of that species not be brought into existence."[19][20] He has also argued that the outbreak of zoonotic diseases, such as the COVID-19 pandemic,[21] is often the result of how humans mistreat animals.[22]
Benatar is an atheist[16][17] and is ethnically Jewish.[23] He has expressed concern about what he views as a hostile environment toward Jews at institutions such as the University of Cape Town, attributing this to elements of what he describes as the "regressive left".[24] He has also expressed criticism of South Africans who have shown support for Hamas, including Ronnie Kasrils.[25]
Bibliography
[edit]- Benatar, David (2001). Ethics for Everyday. McGraw-Hill. ISBN 978-0-07-240889-8.
- Benatar, David (2006). Better Never to Have Been: The Harm of Coming into Existence. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-929642-2.
- Benatar, David (2012). The Second Sexism: Discrimination Against Men and Boys. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-0-470-67451-2.
- Benatar, David (2015). "The Misanthropic Argument for Anti-natalism". In S. Hannan; S. Brennan; R. Vernon (eds.). Permissible Progeny?: The Morality of Procreation and Parenting. Oxford University Press. pp. 34–64. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199378111.003.0002. ISBN 978-0-19-937814-2.
- Benatar, David; Wasserman, David (2015). Debating Procreation: Is It Wrong to Reproduce?. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-027311-8.
- Archard, David; Benatar, David (2016). Procreation and Parenthood: The Ethics of Bearing and Rearing Children. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-874815-1.
- Benatar, David (2017). The Human Predicament: A Candid Guide to Life's Biggest Questions. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-063381-3.
- Benatar, David (2021). The Fall of the University of Cape Town: Africa’s Leading University in Decline. Politicsweb Publishing. ISBN 978-3-9822364-2-1.
- Benatar, David (2024). Very Practical Ethics: Engaging Everyday Moral Questions. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-778079-4.
As editor
[edit]- Benatar, David, ed. (2006). Cutting to the Core: Exploring the Ethics of Contested Surgeries. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-0-7425-5001-8.
- Ethics for Everyday. New York: McGraw-Hill, 2002.
- Life, Death & Meaning: Key Philosophical Readings on the Big Questions (2004)
Notes
[edit]- ^ a b c "Emeritus Professor David Benatar". University of Cape Town. Retrieved 4 May 2025.
- ^ a b Rothman, Joshua (27 November 2017). "The Case for Not Being Born". The New Yorker. ISSN 0028-792X. Retrieved 4 May 2025.
- ^ 7 October, One Year Later with Philosopher David Benatar (Video). 10 October 2024. Event occurs at 0:02.
- ^ "Editorial Board". Journal of Controversial Ideas. Retrieved 20 April 2020.
- ^ Benatar, David (1997). "Why It Is Better Never to Come into Existence". American Philosophical Quarterly. 34 (3): 345–355. ISSN 0003-0481. JSTOR 20009904.
- ^ Benatar 2006, pp. 30–40.
- ^ a b Benatar 2006, pp. 30–57.
- ^ a b Benatar 2006, pp. 64–69.
- ^ Sheffield, Nicholas (21 October 2020). "Determined to Die". Simon Fraser University Undergraduate Journal of Philosophy. 2 (1) – via Philosophy Nouveau.
- ^ Blackburn, Simon (5 July 2012). "The Second Sexism: Discrimination Against Men and Boys". Times Higher Education (THE). Retrieved 4 May 2025.
- ^ Landau, Iddo (2012). "The Second Sexism". Metapsychology. 16 (34).
- ^ Benatar, Michael; Benatar, David (2003). "Between Prophylaxis and Child Abuse: The Ethics of Neonatal Male Circumcision". The American Journal of Bioethics. 3 (2): 35–48. ISSN 1536-0075.
- ^ Benatar, D.; Benatar, M. (February 2001). "A Pain in the Fetus: Toward Ending Confusion about Fetal Pain". Bioethics. 15 (1): 57–76. doi:10.1111/1467-8519.00212. ISSN 0269-9702. PMID 11699550.
- ^ "Works by David Benatar". PhilPapers. Retrieved 4 May 2025.
- ^ Calia, Michael (2 February 2014). "Writer Nic Pizzolatto on Thomas Ligotti and the Weird Secrets of 'True Detective'". The Wall Street Journal. Retrieved 4 May 2025.
- ^ a b "Antinatalism – should we let humanity go extinct? David Benatar vs Bruce Blackshaw". 13 March 2020. Retrieved 14 March 2020 – via YouTube.
- ^ a b "The Harm of Coming Into Existence". 13 June 2020. 8:36 minutes in. Retrieved 13 June 2020 – via YouTube.
- ^ The Species Barrier 35 Antinatal, retrieved 5 March 2023, around 30 minutes in
- ^ Benatar, David (15 July 2015). "'We Are Creatures That Should Not Exist': The Theory of Anti-Natalism". The Critique. Archived from the original on 17 July 2015. Retrieved 4 May 2025.
- ^ Shoemaker, Natalie (18 August 2015). "Do Humans Have a Moral Duty to Stop Procreating?". Big Think. Retrieved 4 May 2025.
- ^ Wiebers, David; Feigin, Valery (1 January 2021). "Heeding the call of COVID-19". Animal Sentience. 5 (30). doi:10.51291/2377-7478.1671. ISSN 2377-7478.
- ^ Benatar, David (13 April 2020). "Opinion | Our Cruel Treatment of Animals Led to the Coronavirus". The New York Times. ISSN 0362-4331. Retrieved 4 May 2025.
- ^ Attwell, David (11 January 2022). "On The fall of the University of Cape Town by David Benatar: a discussion". LitNet (in Afrikaans). Retrieved 4 May 2025.
- ^ Feinberg, Tali (18 November 2021). "UCT has become 'University of Capitulation', says professor". South African Jewish Report. Retrieved 10 April 2024.
- ^ Benatar, David. "Denying 7 October: The Case of Former ANC Minister Ronnie Kasrils". Fathom. Retrieved 10 April 2024.
References
[edit]- "Affirmative Action and UCT – the debate". Monday Paper. Vol. 26, no. 5. University of Cape Town. 23 April 2007. Retrieved 21 February 2011.
- Benatar, David; Benatar, Michael (2001). "A Pain in the Fetus: Toward Ending Confusion about Fetal Pain". Bioethics. 15 (1): 57–76. doi:10.1111/1467-8519.00212. ISSN 0269-9702. PMID 11699550. S2CID 29866864.
- Benatar, Michael; Benatar, David (2003). "Between Prophylaxis and Child Abuse: The Ethics of Neonatal Male Circumcision". The American Journal of Bioethics. 3 (2): 35–48. doi:10.1162/152651603766436216. ISSN 1526-5161. PMID 12859815. S2CID 10798287.
- Gert, Joshua; Costa, Victoria; Dancy, Margaret; Benatar, David (1998). "Corporal Punishment". Social Theory and Practice. 24 (2): 237–260. doi:10.5840/soctheorpract19982423. ISSN 0037-802X. S2CID 40360712.
- Haupt, Adam (14 May 2007). "We dare not erase race from debate". Mail & Guardian. Johannesburg. Retrieved 21 February 2011.
- Kolbert, Elizabeth (9 April 2012). "The Case Against Kids: Is procreation immoral?". The New Yorker. Retrieved 6 April 2012.
- London, Leslie (4 June 2007). "Affirmative action and the invisibility of white privilege". Vol. 26, no. 8. University of Cape Town. Retrieved 21 February 2011.
- Raditlhalo, Sam (25 April 2007). "So much remains hidden behind those plastic smiles at UCT". Cape Times. Archived from the original on 19 April 2023. Retrieved 29 April 2008.
External links
[edit]- David Benatar at IMDb
Quotations related to David Benatar at Wikiquote
- 1966 births
- Living people
- 20th-century South African philosophers
- 21st-century South African male writers
- 21st-century South African non-fiction writers
- 21st-century South African philosophers
- Academic staff of the University of Cape Town
- Animal ethicists
- Anti-natalists
- Bioethicists
- Jewish academics
- Jewish atheists
- Jewish non-fiction writers
- Jewish philosophers
- Philosophers of law
- Philosophers of pessimism
- Philosophers of religion
- Scholars of veganism
- South African atheists
- Social philosophers
- South African ethicists
- South African male non-fiction writers
- University of Cape Town alumni
- 20th-century South African Jews
- 21st-century South African Jews
- South African secular Jews