Jump to content

Ethical hedonism

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Ethical hedonism is a branch of hedonism, the philosophical theory that identifies pleasure as the highest good and the proper aim of human life. While hedonism can take many forms, ethical hedonism specifically refers to the normative claim that individuals ought to pursue pleasure and avoid pain because pleasure is the only intrinsic good. This view contrasts with psychological hedonism, which makes a descriptive claim about human nature—that people are naturally motivated by the pursuit of pleasure and the avoidance of pain.[1] Ethical hedonism goes further by asserting that the pursuit of pleasure is not only natural but also morally right. It has been historically defended by philosophers such as Epicurus, and later developed by utilitarians like Jeremy Bentham, John Stuart Mill, and Henry Sidgwick, who argued that maximizing pleasure and minimizing pain forms the basis of ethical behavior.[2][3]

Overview

[edit]

Ethical hedonism holds that pleasure is the highest moral good, and the pursuit of pleasure is central to living a good life. The theory has two main components: first, it argues that pleasure is the sole intrinsic good, and second, that individuals should strive to maximize pleasure. The theory comes in two main forms: egoistic and altruistic. Egoistic ethical hedonism holds that individuals should seek their own pleasure, while altruistic ethical hedonism suggests that individuals should aim to maximize pleasure for others or for everyone.[4]

Ethical hedonism is linked to the broader philosophical system of utilitarianism, which also bases moral decisions on the principle of maximizing happiness. Thinkers such as Jeremy Bentham, John Stuart Mill, and Henry Sidgwick were proponents of ethical hedonism, advocating that pleasure and pain serve as the moral compass for determining right and wrong actions.[5]

Prudential hedonism

[edit]

Prudential hedonism is a form of ethical hedonism focused on individual well-being. It holds that pleasure is the only ultimate good in a person’s life, and pain the only ultimate bad. The best life, therefore, is the one with the greatest net pleasure—pleasure minus pain. Unlike other ethical theories, prudential hedonism does not prescribe how or when pleasure should be pursued. Whether through sensory enjoyment or spiritual discipline, any approach is acceptable if it increases net pleasure. It is also neutral on the source or timing of pleasure—immediate or delayed, social or solitary. What matters is the outcome: a life with more pleasure than pain.[4]

Arguments in support

[edit]

The reliability argument

[edit]

One key argument in favor of ethical hedonism is the Reliability Argument. This argument suggests that phenomenal introspection, or the direct awareness of one's experience, reliably reveals pleasure as a good. In contrast, other moral beliefs arise from unreliable processes shaped by evolution and cultural variation. As pleasure consistently enhances our experience, it is argued that pleasure is an objective moral good.[6]

The universality argument

[edit]

Another argument is the Universality Argument, which claims that all moral agents should respond to positive experiences with pleasure. It asserts that pleasure is a universal indicator of goodness, as it consistently makes experiences feel better. From this perspective, responding to pleasure and pain aligns moral actions with natural goodness across all human perspectives.[6]

Distinction from psychological hedonism

[edit]

While psychological hedonism posits that humans naturally pursue pleasure as a fundamental drive, ethical hedonism is a prescriptive theory that asserts people ought to pursue pleasure. Psychological hedonism is a descriptive theory about human behavior, whereas ethical hedonism adds a moral dimension, guiding individuals on how they should behave in order to lead a good life.[7]

Historical development

[edit]

Epicurus

[edit]

The ancient Greek philosopher Epicurus is one of the most prominent advocates of ethical hedonism. In his writings, particularly the Letter to Menoeceus, he argues that pleasure is the ultimate goal of life and should be pursued rationally. Epicurus emphasizes katastematic pleasures—pleasures of bodily health (aponia) and mental tranquility (ataraxia)—as the most desirable, and distinguishes between natural and necessary desires and unnecessary desires. Epicurus promotes a form of ethical hedonism that incorporates reason and reflection to ensure long-term peace and happiness.[8]

Modern thinkers

[edit]

In the 18th and 19th centuries, philosophers such as Jeremy Bentham, John Stuart Mill, and Henry Sidgwick further developed ethical hedonism within the framework of utilitarianism. They argued that the best moral actions are those that maximize overall happiness and pleasure. Bentham's utilitarianism, for example, suggests that pleasure is the basis of moral value and that individuals should act to promote the greatest amount of pleasure for the greatest number of people.[9][4]

Criticism

[edit]

Paradox of hedonism

[edit]

One notable challenge to ethical hedonism is the Paradox of Hedonism, which suggests that directly pursuing pleasure may be self-defeating. This paradox asserts that the more one focuses on achieving pleasure, the less likely they are to attain it. It points to the possibility that excessive pursuit of pleasure can lead to diminishing returns and could undermine the overall goal of achieving lasting happiness.[4]

Selfishness and altruism

[edit]

Ethical hedonism, particularly egoistic hedonism, has been criticized for promoting selfishness. Critics argue that a focus on personal pleasure may lead to unethical behavior, as individuals could prioritize their own desires over the well-being of others. In contrast, altruistic hedonism seeks to balance individual pleasure with the greater good, but some critics argue that this does not fully address the complexities of moral decision-making.[9][4]

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ "Hedonism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 10 May 2025.
  2. ^ Mill, John Stuart (1863). Utilitarianism. London: Parker, Son, and Bourn.
  3. ^ Sidgwick, Henry (1874). The Methods of Ethics. London: Macmillan.
  4. ^ a b c d e "Hedonism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 10 May 2025.
  5. ^ "Utilitarianism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 10 May 2025.
  6. ^ a b "Naturalistic Arguments for Ethical Hedonism". Utilitarianism.net. Retrieved 10 May 2025.
  7. ^ "Ethics of Hedonism" (PDF). Bidhannagar College. Retrieved 10 May 2025.
  8. ^ Waggle, Larry J. (December 2007). "Epicurus: Psychological or Ethical Hedonist?". Revista de Filosofía. 25 (57): 73–88. Retrieved 10 May 2025.
  9. ^ a b "Hedonism: Definition, Theories & Criticism". Study.com. Retrieved 10 May 2025.